Critical studies on the animal question are practically unanimous in relating the intensification of animal exploitation to the capitalist mode of production. Nevertheless, the vast majority of Marxists are unaware of this discussion, and eco-socialism itself is rather timid in punctuating the contradictions regarding animal abuse, as can be seen in the International Ecosocialist Manifesto, which at no time mentions the animal issue.
Because animals lack the ability to enjoy freedom in the Marxist – political – sense, they cannot contribute to the social relations of production, and because they are sentient, they should not be treated as mere objects of human labour. They can, however, enjoy the freedom of nature, which is their fundamental right, as natural beings.
"Evolution of Revolution”, by Hartmut Kiewert, 2013
Critical studies on the animal question are practically unanimous in
relating the intensification of animal exploitation to the capitalist mode
of production. Nevertheless, the vast majority of Marxists are unaware of
this discussion, and eco-socialism itself is rather timid in punctuating the
contradictions regarding animal abuse, as can be seen in the International
Ecosocialist Manifesto,1 which at no time mentions the animal issue.
Analyses of the relationship between humans and other animals are
hegemonized by liberal and poststructuralist theories, which the Marxist
philosopher Marco Maurizi calls “metaphysical anti-speciesism”.2 According
to Maurizi, they are moralizing and disregard the totality of the historical
processes which led to the systematic exploitation of animals, placing the
human being as generically responsible for this social practice.
In the academic field, the struggle for animals also focuses on movements in
conformity with bourgeois society, partly as a result of the predominance of
liberal ideology, but also of Marxist neglect regarding the degrading
situation in which animals under the custody of capitalist industry are
found.
A forerunner of the “animalist” debate within Marxism, Ted Benton,3 was one
of those responsible for criticizing the anthropocentric characteristic of
Marxian work. The defence against this criticism has been highlighted in the
works of Foster, Stache, Clark4 and Saito,5 claiming that, contrary to the
accusations of Benton and other ecologists, Marx was one of the first to
point out the metabolic disruption between man and nature, caused by
capitalism.6
In spite of Marx having written about the objective consequences of land and
the alienation of man from nature ,7 he did not focus on studying the
relationship between humans and other sentient beings. This was not the
first time that Marx would have overlooked a determinant category for the
emergence and maintenance of capitalism, as he did in relation to unpaid
work of women in social reproduction.8
It is evident, nevertheless, that Marxist anthropocentrism is concerned with
the centrality of human historical activity as a transformer of its
environment and sociability, and not of contempt for other animals. When
Marx raises human activity to the level of planned work compared to the
instinctual work of other animals,9 he exposes the differences between both
activities and at no time invokes a natural right of humankind to other
animals due to the fact of the latter’s work be mostly immediate.
In short, the debate regarding whether Marx was speciesist or not is
irrelevant, since being anachronistic it must not overlap with the
historicity of animal manipulation. Historical materialism seeks to
understand a time and its phenomena based on its mode of production and its
consolidation throughout history. Hence, the lack of Marxian animal studies,
shouldn’t be more important than the animal exploitation itself, which is
one of the most common and naturalized social practices in the current mode
of production.
The vast Marxian work counts with various references to animals, all of
which are descriptive or comparative, such as when he describes the
expulsion of peasants for the transformation of their crops into sheep
pastures in England, or when he tries to explain, through the activity of
bees, the difference between human labour and the work of other animals.10
It is evident, however, the predominance of an unconcerned narrative towards
them. Descartes’ mechanistic materialism, which compared animals to
clocks,11 still influenced the thinking of the time and it was fundamental
in legitimizing the use of animals as inanimate goods by the new capitalist
order.12 In other words, we do not exploit animals because we think they are
inferior, on the contrary, we consider animals as inferior because we
exploit them.13
In addition, the commodification of animals in the nineteenth century and
earlier centuries took place on a much smaller scale than we know nowadays
and has developed as technological improvements and transformations in the
mode of production evolved. As capitalism advanced, animals were no longer
used primarily for the purposes of certain forms of social reproduction
(feeding, traction, clothing and transportation, etc.) – but instead were
used as means of production for the purpose of accumulation and value
aggregation.14 The food, pharmaceutical, cosmetic and fashion industries are
currently the largest animal exploiters and together they make up one of the
world’s leading economic sectors. They are responsible for the
incarceration, torture, mutilation, sexual exploitation and death of
billions of animals every year. In the agrarian sector alone, the animal
industry is responsible for 40% of world revenues and for the predominance
of land use.15
Nowadays there is consensus on the well-being of pets. These, included in
the sphere of moral consideration and consumption – through their tutors –
are not subject to the systematic and widespread exploitation which animals
owned by capitalists suffer. The domestic animal is even considered as a
family member, a resident of the house, having its interests normally met,
its emotions considered and its comfort and safety normally guaranteed,
which even configures a new type of household. Homeless animals also rely on
the population’s efforts to be sheltered and fed, even if this is not always
objectively possible. Besides, pets are usually protected against abuse by
law. On the other hand, animals that are domesticated by the industry are
viewed as commodities by capitalists. They are sold as processed products,
separated from their living and sentient origin and all the harmful
processes of production. Fetishism, in this case, not only dehumanizes by
suppressing all the work contained in those so-called commodities and by
alienating both the worker, whose duty it is to kill, and the consumer. It
also de-animalizes them by depriving the animals of their natural life,
disregarding their sentience, exploiting and slaughtering them to be
transformed into a product for the purpose of capital accumulation.
Due to the impossibility of animals organizing themselves to resist the
oppression they suffer, they are taken as natural resources that are
transformed into a means of production. Because they are not labour sellers
or consumers, animals cannot independently integrate economically into
bourgeois society. This difference puts them at a disadvantage compared to
other oppressed groups, even the most oppressed among humans, who are able
to organize and claim their interests collectively.16 This difference is
what makes humans the subjects of their own liberation, whilst animals are
objects of liberation.17
The autonomous instinct for animals is to resist individually. In this
sense, it is through the bourgeois state that control over animals is
ensured in order to meet the interests of corporations.18 Capitalists are
permitted to indulge in the most degrading practices to contain the
resistance and the natural behaviour of animals, ignoring their ability to
suffer. These practices include – but are not limited to – incarceration and
mutilation and are considered as legitimate ways to prevent injury and death
by the scientific and legal community.19
The infliction of suffering in order to contain the natural expression of
the animal masks itself as an ethical measure by alleging to prevent animals
from being injured, when in fact it is about avoiding damage to the value of
the asset.20 These measures aim to remedy a situation of conflict caused by
the capitalist industry itself by imposing an extremely artificial way of
life on animals that are natural. In the end, these same animals will be
injured and killed when it is in the owner’s interest that their raw
material be transformed into products.
Lukács reminds us that Marx has always criticized every romantic veneration
for the less evolved past, every attempt to employ it against objectively
superior developments.21 He also highlights the gigantic difference between
becoming the other through a spontaneous and involuntary biological process
of adaptation to new natural facts or as a result of one’s own social
praxis.22 In this sense, the exploratory relationship between humans and
other animals is part of a spontaneous process, which in the past took place
in a metabolic way, evolving to become a social practice that met the needs
of the growing population and which, in the last century, has become a
destructive economic practice due to the endless profit capitalist essence.
This practice no longer corresponds to natural or historical needs, due to
the development of the forces of production, which would enable other ways
to obtain food and other resources that we previously obtained through
animals, at the cost of their suffering and withdrawal of their autonomy.
Modern technology outperforms the animal industry with respect to the
production of organic and synthetic materials, as well as agroecology,
proposed by social movements for land reform and use,23 outperforms
agribusiness for its effectiveness in relation to soil recovery,
preservation of biodiversity, total production and, consequently, food
quality.24
Malm affirms that presenting certain social relations as if they were
natural properties of the species is not new. De-historicizing,
universalizing and naturalizing a specific mode of production of a given
time and place are part of the classic strategies of ideological
legitimation.25 By no means is any human social practice justified in
itself, since already detached from immediate natural needs, human practices
are historical and, therefore, political. Revolutionary praxis proposes to
overcome the spontaneity of common sense in order to instead build a
critical and coherent conception of the world. The current level of
development of the productive forces allows us to think about resolving the
issue of animal suffering and its inclusion in the struggle for
emancipation, since the further we move from animality and the more we
develop our ability to modify our environment and our form of sociability,
the more obsolete the barbaric treatment of animals becomes.
It must be recognized, moreover, that due to ecological and social damage,
the animal industries are irrational. The conversion of these industries
into forms of production where we do not see the world through its
commodities – but rather through its essence, as an ecologically
sustainable, vegan and socially planned production – would be an appropriate
socialist demand.26
Marxist animal abolitionism therefore comprises the abolition of animal
exploitation not through individual initiatives but through the end of
private ownership of the means of production and their rational
reorganization — at which time animals could be removed from the production
relations with no harm to our own kind. However, while Marxism criticizes
the overestimation of individual initiative by bourgeois liberal conceptions
of the world, the revolutionary daily practice cannot be turned into a
caricature, as Lukács reiterates.27 In this sense, “veganism is part of a
revolutionary perspective”, Angela Davis affirms,28 and it is also important
for the exercise of solidarity and denaturalization of oppressive practices
by the working class. Furthermore, the issue of animal products is not just
a matter of consumption, as such products are problematic in themselves due
to the inherent violence involved in their production, regardless of the
political and economic system in which it occurs.
Besides, fruitful debates and dialogues can be generated among the working
class with concrete examples that it is possible to live in a dignified way
without violating any animals. It is not the role of Marxists to soften the
perception of the conflict between the capitalist mode of production and the
welfare of humans, other animals and the natural environment. On the
contrary, it is by highlighting and elucidating these conflicts and their
everyday perception that working people turn to themselves. If animals are
not part of our class because they are not humans, they are not part of the
ruling class either, and they have much more in common with us than with
them, whether that is in terms of exploitation, freedom deprivation or
commoditization. The communist morality, as a development of the proletarian
morality envisioned by Engels,29 can only be built on the rejection of all
forms of oppression.30 Thus, considering the present relations of
production, we must reject animal exploitation, incorporating the struggle
for their liberation into the struggle for human emancipation, since there
is no justification, other than bourgeois moralism, for the industrial
application of suffering on animals.
Because animals lack the ability to enjoy freedom in the Marxist – political
– sense, they cannot contribute to the social relations of production, and
because they are sentient, they should not be treated as mere objects of
human labour. They can, however, enjoy the freedom of nature, which is their
fundamental right, as natural beings. The commitment of revolutionary praxis
is to build the new and not to worship the traditions based on oppression.
As Marx wrote in his youth, quoting Thomas Müntzer: “the creatures, too,
must become free”.31
References
Originally published in Lavra Palavra (in Portuguese): O Marxismo e a Questão Animal