By Joan Dunayer
Reprinted with the author's permission, September 2015
Originally published in The Vegan,
Summer 2005, pp.
14-16
Copyright 2005 Joan Dunayer
It’s speciesist to deny any nonhuman being equal consideration and respect either because they aren’t human or because they aren’t human-like.
Whenever you see a parrot in a cage, goldfish in a tank, or dog on a
chain, you’re seeing speciesism. If you believe that a turtle or wasp has
less right to life and liberty than a fox or human, or you consider humans
superior to other animals, you subscribe to speciesism. If you visit
aquaprisons and zoos, wear cow skin and sheep hair, or eat flesh, eggs, or
cow-milk products, you practice speciesism.
Old Speciesism
What exactly is speciesism? Psychologist Richard Ryder coined the word
speciesism in 1970. Although he didn’t explicitly define the term, he
indicated that speciesists draw a sharp moral distinction between humans and
all other animals.[1] Similarly to Ryder, philosophers Peter Singer and Tom
Regan define speciesism as bias against all nonhumans.[2] That definition is
too narrow. Racism isn’t restricted to bias against all nonwhites; it
encompasses bias against any number of races (for example, against all
nonwhites except for Asians, against only blacks and native Americans, or
against only Australian aborigines). Analogously, speciesism isn’t limited
to bias against all nonhumans; it includes bias against any number of animal
species, such as all animals other than great apes, all nonmammals, or all
invertebrates.
What Ryder, Singer, and Regan call “speciesism” actually is only one type of
speciesism: the oldest and most severe form, which I call “old speciesism.”
Old-speciesists don’t believe that any nonhumans should receive as much
moral consideration as humans or have basic legal rights, such as rights to
life and liberty. Most humans are old-speciesists.
New Speciesism
In contrast to old-speciesists, a growing number of people believe that
moral and legal rights should extend beyond our species. However, most of
these people are not egalitarian; they display a brand of speciesism that I
term “new speciesism.” New-speciesists favor rights for only some nonhumans,
those who seem most human-like. Believing that most humans are superior to
all nonhumans, new-speciesists see animalkind as a hierarchy with humans at
the top. Typically they regard chimpanzees, dolphins, and other select
nonhuman mammals as more important than other nonhumans. They also rank
mammals above birds; birds above reptiles, amphibians, and fishes; and
vertebrates above invertebrates.
Singer exemplifies new speciesism. In his view humans of at least normal
intelligence have more value than any nonhumans.[3] Moreover, he advocates a
right to life and liberty only for humans, other great apes, and possibly
other mammals, provided that they possess as much self-awareness as a normal
human beyond earliest infancy.[4] Why a normal human? Why not a normal
octopus or crow? Singer’s criterion clearly is human-centered and
human-biased: speciesist. Singer deems all nonmammals “replaceable” (his
word).[5] He isn’t categorically opposed to vivisection on nonmammals.[6]
Also, he considers it morally acceptable to rear birds, fishes, and other
nonmammals for slaughter if their lives are pleasant (extremely unlikely)
and they’re killed quickly and painlessly (also extremely unlikely).[7] “It
is not speciesist,” he claims, to think that the killing of several thousand
humans is “more tragic” than the killing of several million chickens.[8] Of
course it’s speciesist.
Nonspeciesism
Rejecting the notion of human superiority, nonspeciesists advocate basic
rights for all sentient beings. Nonspeciesists don’t want relatively few
nonhumans to be honorary humans; they want sentience to replace humanness as
the basis for rights.
Sentience should suffice for basic legal rights because anyone who can
experience has an interest in staying alive and faring well, and the whole
point of laws is to protect interests.[9] In the eyes of the law, the most
mentally incompetent humans have interests that warrant protection. Further,
their interests don’t count for less than those of humans with normal or
high IQs. Humans who lack language and abstract reasoning still have rights.
So why shouldn’t all nonhuman beings also have rights? Consciousness of any
type and degree creates a need for protection. Any sentient being loses
everything when they die. Any sentient being can suffer. Freedom from
deprivation and pain is as relevant to lobsters and snakes as to gorillas
and humans.
Nonspeciesists envision all nonhuman beings as legal persons rather than
human property. Personhood would emancipate nonhumans from servitude to
humans, who couldn’t legally compel nonhumans to labor, perform, compete, or
provide any service. No longer would horses pull carriages, tigers jump
through hoops, or elephants bear humans on their backs. The law would
prohibit human ownership of nonhumans. Humans couldn’t breed, buy, or sell
nonhumans for any purpose, from vivisection and food production to pet
keeping and the propagation of endangered species.
By the time of emancipation, a much larger percentage of the public would
support animal equality and be vegan than today, so far fewer nonhumans
would be captive. Upon emancipation dogs, cats, and other “domesticated”
animals living with loving, responsible human companions would stay with
those humans.[10] Liberated from exploitation and other abuse, other
“domesticated” animals—such as chickens freed from egg factories and rats
freed from vivisection labs—would receive any needed veterinary care, be
euthanized if experiencing apparently incurable suffering, and otherwise be
fostered at sanctuaries and private homes until adopted. Nonhumans in human
care would have essentially the same legal rights as children.
Nonhuman captivity would be phased out. To the fullest possible extent,
“domesticated” animals (including dogs and cats) would be prevented from
breeding—for example, through surgical “neutering.”[11] The number of
“domesticated” animals would rapidly decline.
Non-“domesticated” captives would be set free if, after any necessary
rehabilitation, they could thrive without human assistance and if
appropriate habitat existed. If not, they would be permanently cared for at
sanctuaries. As much as possible these sanctuaries would provide natural,
fulfilling environments. Like “domesticated” animals, non-“domesticated”
captives would be prevented from breeding. Eventually, virtually all
nonhumans would be non-“domesticated” animals living, free of human
interference, in natural habitats.
Full personhood would give nonhumans all relevant legal rights, such as a
right to life. Like all other nonhuman rights, a nonhuman right to life
would constrain human, not nonhuman, behavior. Humans wouldn’t interfere
with predator–prey relationships among free-living nonhumans. Unlike humans,
predators must kill prey to survive. Under nonspeciesist law it would be
illegal for a human to intentionally kill a nonhuman except under
extraordinary circumstances. If you were stranded in a frozen wasteland or
famine-stricken area devoid of plant food and you faced imminent starvation,
you’d be entitled to kill an animal for food. If a lion were leaping at your
throat, you’d be entitled to kill in self-defense. You’d be free to kill
internal parasites threatening a dog’s health and free to euthanize a cat
experiencing incurable suffering. In contrast, it would be illegal to kill
mice for experimental data, cattle for their flesh, fishes for sport, minks
for their pelts, spiders out of aversion, or any other nonhumans for
uncompelling reasons.
Personhood would give nonhumans a right to liberty: physical freedom and
bodily integrity. With the temporary exception of “domesticated” animals,
and some non-“domesticated” animals captive at the time of emancipation,
nonhumans would have complete liberty. Humans couldn’t legally hold them
captive by chaining, caging, fencing, confining to a building, or any other
means. It would be illegal to torture or sexually assault a nonhuman, as
well as to maim, batter, or otherwise injure a nonhuman except in someone’s
direct defense.
Nonspeciesist law also would accord nonhumans a right to property. They
would own the products of their bodies and labors. Oysters would own the
pearls they create, robins the eggs they lay, and honeybee colonies the
honey they produce. Nonhumans would own their nests, burrows, and hives. A
dam built by a family of beavers would belong to those beavers and their
descendents. It would be illegal for humans to take, intentionally damage,
or intentionally destroy anything that nonhumans produce within their
natural habitats. Further, nonhumans would own their habitats. All nonhumans
living in a particular area of land or water would have a legal right to
that environment, which would be their communal property. Land currently
inhabited by nonhumans and humans could remain cohabited, but humans
wouldn’t be permitted to encroach farther into nonhuman territory (for
instance, by building more houses on land occupied only by nonhumans). It
would be illegal to intentionally destroy or dramatically alter any
“undeveloped” habitat.
To be equitable, the law must be nonspeciesist. The vast majority of the
world’s living beings are nonhuman. Speciesism is the most deeply entrenched
and harmful form of injustice.
Both an attitude and a practice, speciesism includes any prejudice or
discrimination based on species. It’s speciesist to deny any nonhuman being
equal consideration and respect either because they aren’t human or because
they aren’t human-like. In terms of their right to justice, all sentient
beings are equal. They not only have a moral right to life and freedom from
abuse; they have an equal right.
Notes
1. See Richard Ryder, “An Autobiography,” Between the Species,
Summer 1992, 168–73, at 171.
2. See Peter Singer, Animal Liberation, 2d ed. (New York: New York
Review of Books, 1990), 6; Tom Regan, “The Case for Animal Rights,” in Carl
Cohen and Tom Regan, The Animal Rights Debate (Lanham, Md.: Rowman
& Littlefield, 2001), 125–222, at 170.
3. See Singer, Animal Liberation, 19–21.
4. See Paola Cavalieri, Peter Singer, et al., “A Declaration on Great Apes,”
in The Great Ape Project: Equality beyond Humanity, ed. Paola
Cavalieri and Peter Singer (New York: St. Martin’s, 1993), 4–7, at 4;
Singer, Animal Liberation, 19–21, 228–29; Peter Singer, Practical
Ethics, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 90, 95, 101,
119–20, 131–32.
5. Singer, Practical Ethics, 131.
6. See Joan Dunayer, Speciesism (Derwood, Md.: Ryce, 2004), 78–79.
7. See Singer, Animal Liberation, 229–30; Singer, Practical Ethics,
133.
8. Peter Singer, “Animal Equality: Language and Liberation by Joan
Dunayer”
(book review), Vegan Voice, Dec. 2001–Feb. 2002, 36.
9. Lacking awareness, insentient things such as plants and rocks have no
interests. When we safeguard natural objects, we do so for the sake of
sentient beings, human and nonhuman.
10. The term domesticated appears in quotation marks because it euphemizes
longstanding captivity and genetic manipulation.
11. The word neutering somewhat misleads. Removing the testicles or the
ovaries and uterus does not, of course, render an animal genderless
(neuter).
Joan Dunayer is the author of Animal Equality: Language and Liberation (2001) and Speciesism (2004).
Return to Animal Rights Articles