Should We Try to Alleviate the Suffering of Wild Animals?
Image: David Selbert/Pexels
As a long-time field researcher, I've seen my share of pain, suffering,
and death in various wild animals stemming from injuries incurred when
running through wild environs, various sorts of altercations, and becoming a
meal. I've always been plagued by trying to figure out if I or my field
assistants should do anything when there was no reason to think that we had
anything to do with what was happening to these unfortunate individuals.
However, this isn't always the case, and humans can intentionally or
unintentionally harm wild animals, and researchers themselves can have
strongly negative effects on the physical and emotional lives of the animals
they're studying (see
Bad Science Adversely Affects Animals' Emotions and Reality).
The sad fact is that injuries and death naturally occur among wild animals,
and that's part of what it is to be one of these amazing beings. We never
did intervene in their lives because their injuries occurred naturally as
they did the things they needed to do. Needless to say, we all hated to see
the suffering of various prey animals hunted by wild coyotes, animals who
were severely beaten up by others, Adélie penguins leaping out of the ocean
after being ripped apart by leopard seals or killer whales, or individuals
injuring themselves when running around, tripping, or colliding with rocks
or cactuses. We felt that once we intervened, we became part of their lives,
and there was no way we could always be there to help all individuals who
needed assistance.
Because I've long thought about the different sorts of responsibilities we
have to wild animals, I learned a lot by reading the highly acclaimed book
Animal Ethics in the Wild: Wild Animal Suffering and Intervention in
Nature by philosopher Dr. Catia Faria, and I believe it should be required
reading for field researchers and anyone who spends a lot of time outdoors
watching other animals. Here's what she had to say about her deeply
thoughtful book.
Why did you write Animal Ethics in the Wild?
I started writing "Animal Ethics in the Wild" because I recognized the
importance of addressing the moral problem of wild animal suffering, which
had been largely overlooked in the field. In a nutshell: Wild animals suffer
too. Should we help them? (Also see Should We "Nudge Nature" to Help Animals
Save Themselves? for a discussion of some of the themes about which Catia
writes and also Paul Taylor's book Respect for Nature, a must-read
for figuring out when and if we should interfere in the lives of other
animals.)
The research I conducted during my PhD thesis laid the groundwork for this
book, and with the encouragement of my viva committee and others, I expanded
upon it to create a more comprehensive publication that was ultimately
accepted by Cambridge University Press.
Entering the field, I was already firmly convinced of the moral case
against animal suffering. If we acknowledge the importance of animal
suffering, it becomes our responsibility to prevent or alleviate it whenever
possible. I find it perplexing that some individuals struggle to grasp this
fundamental idea. Personally, I have always found it challenging to fully
appreciate the beauty of nature due to the moral horrors that lie beneath
its surface. Even a simple walk in the woods serves as a constant reminder
of the suffering present in seemingly "healthy ecosystems." Behind the
idyllic facade of natural landscapes, wild animals face excruciating deaths
as they become prey to predators, suffer from parasites, endure starvation,
and succumb to diseases. Once we confront the reality of wild animal
suffering, ignoring it becomes truly impossible.
It is disheartening to see how this crucial moral issue has been overlooked
in the animal ethics literature for so long, persisting as the "greatest
taboo in animal rights advocacy" until recently (see
Golden).
Considering the profound significance of the topic, its widespread neglect,
and my own personal horror in the face of wild animal suffering, it felt
imperative to delve into animal ethics in the wild.
How does your book relate to your background and general areas of
interest?
As I mentioned before, my concern for wild animal suffering naturally stems
from a broader concern for animal suffering as a whole. After all, suffering
is inherently negative for any being who experiences it, regardless of its
cause or location. The case for wild animal suffering also relates to my
work on the tensions between environmental ethics and animal ethics, making
the case for reevaluating and ultimately abandoning the prevailing intuition
to "leave nature alone." By delving into the intricacies of wild animal
suffering and its moral implications, it reveals that simply leaving nature
untouched does not guarantee the absence of suffering or promote animal
well-being. Ignoring the suffering that exists in the natural world
perpetuates a cycle of indifference and allows unnecessary harm to persist.
Moreover, the issue of wild animal suffering intertwines with my concerns
regarding feminist perspectives on animal issues, particularly ecofeminism.
While ecofeminism has played a significant role in highlighting the
patriarchal domination of nonhuman animals, it often assumes that natural
processes among wild animals fall outside our moral responsibility. This
assumption arises from an idyllic view of nature, overlooking the need for
compassion towards wild animals impacted by natural events. Neglecting their
suffering, I argue, not only fails these animals but also perpetuates a
male-biased worldview.
This male-biased worldview is reflected in an extreme hands-off approach
that aligns with the masculine stereotype of emotional restraint and a lack
of personal involvement with those in need. However, countering the
anthropocentric and male-biased paradigm of intervention in nature should
not lead us to adopt a laissez-faire attitude. Instead, it should guide us
toward a gender-sensitive approach to the ethics of our interventions within
the natural world.
Who is your intended audience?
The book has a wide-ranging audience in mind, encompassing scholars
specializing in animal ethics, environmental ethics, and ethics as a whole.
It accommodates readers with varying levels of familiarity with the topic,
welcoming both those well-versed in the field and newcomers alike.
Nevertheless, its target goes beyond academia and aims to resonate with
animal advocates actively dedicated to promoting animal well-being. The book
strives to provide these advocates with analytic resources to effectively
articulate their moral beliefs and contribute to positive change for wild
animals. Furthermore, it invites individuals from all backgrounds who
possess a genuine interest in addressing and alleviating suffering on a
broader scale. My sincere hope is that anyone driven to make a meaningful
impact in the world will discover inspiration and valuable insights within
this book.
What are some of the topics you weave into your book and what are
some of your major messages?
The first part of the book delves into fundamental discussions of animal
ethics, including the moral consideration of nonhuman animals, the
significance of their well-being, and a critical examination of speciesism.
These explorations serve as a foundation upon which I build a minimal case
for intervening in nature to mitigate wild animal suffering.
Drawing directly from widely accepted moral beliefs and backed by relevant
facts about the lives of wild animals, I argue that intervening in nature
becomes an imperative when we acknowledge our reasons to help and fully
recognize the moral worth of nonhuman animals. After all, most people
believe that we should help others in need due to natural events. But what
about starving, wounded and sick wild animals, shouldn’t we also help them?
If nonhuman suffering matters, wild animal suffering matters too and we
should do something about it whenever we can. This conclusion gains further
support from the contention that suffering is likely pervasive in the lives
of wild animals, which may come as an unexpected but significant revelation.
Various factors contribute to wild animal suffering, including the wasteful
reproductive strategies adopted by the majority of wild animals and the
multitude of natural threats to their health, physical well-being, and
psychological integrity. The primary aim of such intervention is thus to
alleviate the extensive suffering experienced by wild animals to the
greatest extent possible. Their suffering matters, just as ours does, and
it's our responsibility to take action whenever we can. It's a
straightforward proposition, isn't it?
As mentioned earlier, there is a significant number of people who struggle
to accept this fundamental proposition. Therefore, a substantial portion of
the book is dedicated to addressing various objections that have been raised
or could potentially be raised against it. To navigate through these
objections, I take Albert O. Hirschman's map of the opposition to social
progress and identify six primary sets of objections that form the core of
the case against intervention in nature.
One concern is that intervention could backfire and have counterproductive
consequences. But, of course, this ignores something crucial: that
intervention should be performed only when the expected outcome is net
positive for wild animals. By recognizing the need to alleviate suffering in
the wild, we are compelled to carefully evaluate the consequences of
intervention. Another concern regards how intervention might pose risks to
other values that are deemed more important, such as ‘the natural’ Yet, and
this is perhaps one of central messages of the book, if you think we should
always "leave nature alone” and you genuinely care about the suffering of
other animals, you simply can't have it both ways.
Now, another common objection is that addressing wild animal suffering might
be an insurmountable challenge or simply impossible to achieve. Wild animal
suffering is not an insurmountable challenge, even if interventions to
reduce it now are often infeasible. To label certain interventions as
infeasible simply indicates that we currently lack the knowledge or means to
achieve them. Feasibility should not be seen as something static, but rather
as dynamic and conditional upon our efforts to try. From this, it follows
that we ought to put ourselves in a position, both individually and
collectively, to develop future safe and effective solutions to the plight
of wild animals. This can be accomplished by fostering the development of
welfare biology as a distinct field of research. Welfare biology is a
systematic discipline that revolves around the study of sentient organisms
and their well-being. Its primary objective is to understand the factors and
relations that affect the welfare of these organisms, focusing on strategies
that can contribute to their overall improvement. Moreover, this notion is
only partially true, as there are already feasible, low-impact interventions
available that can make a difference. For instance, we have witnessed
successful vaccination programs implemented for wild animals to combat
diseases like rabies or tuberculosis for several decades. In national parks,
additional food is occasionally provided to starving animals, ensuring their
survival. These examples, among many others, illustrate the feasibility of
interventions to alleviate wild animal suffering. Moreover, they imply that
there is potential for numerous other interventions to be successfully
implemented.
It is important to note though that the fundamental discussion does not
solely revolve around the interventions that are already available. Rather,
the focus lies in examining whether we have moral reasons to develop the
means to increasingly make these interventions more feasible. The scale of
the problem is clearly enormous and our current capacity for action is
fairly limited. Much more work is needed on different fronts to address this
crucial moral topic. Yet, we should be wary of not over-focusing on
practical issues and minimising the question of how to develop the
appropriate moral attitudes which will make it increasingly feasible to
provide wild animals with the care they need. This is, in my view, the
greatest obstacle to tackling the problem wild animal suffering. "Animal
Ethics in the Wild" aims to contribute to this necessary moral shift. While
there is much work to be done, it is my hope that through collective
efforts, we can make progress and pave the way for a future where the
welfare of wild animals is given the attention and care it truly deserves.
How does your book differ from others that are concerned with some
of the same general topics?
My book provides a comprehensive treatment of the moral debate surrounding
the specific issue at hand. In contrast, some other books may not
exclusively dedicate themselves to this particular issue or offer as
comprehensive of an exploration of the moral debate. They may also address
the political dimension of the problem or focus on implementation issues.
While these perspectives are valuable and important, my book emphasizes the
ethical case as its primary focus. My aim is to help readers cultivate the
right moral attitudes toward suffering of wild animals. This, in turn, can
contribute to making the implementation of the best solutions increasingly
feasible in the future. I believe that by establishing a strong ethical
foundation, we can make informed decisions and navigate the complex
challenges of reducing wild animal suffering more effectively.
Are you hopeful that as people learn more about wild animal
suffering they will be more sensitive to the issue?
Clearly, people can only exhibit compassion towards a reality that they are
aware of. When I first started working on the issue of wild animal
suffering, I held a somewhat naive belief that as people gained a deeper
understanding of the subject, they would naturally become more attuned and
sensitive to the issue. This led me to dedicate a significant portion of my
activism towards challenging the idyllic view of nature that portrays wild
animals as leading blissful lives, only occasionally disrupted by human
interference. In many ways, I believe I was partially correct in this
assumption.
However, in recent years, I have become increasingly skeptical. I must admit
that there is a powerful narrative, often supported by an environmentalist
agenda, that fosters a sense of indifference towards individual wild
animals, even in light of the substantial information available. It seems to
be a strategy that replaces an "absence of awareness" with an "absence of
care." This realization has given rise to my growing skepticism about the
effectiveness of empirical knowledge alone in driving compassionate action
for wild animal welfare.
Can you say something about when we shouldn't interfere -- maybe
that's something you write about?
As discussed earlier, the scope of large-scale interventions aimed at
reducing wild animal suffering is presently quite limited. Consequently,
there are instances where interference may not be advisable due to our
current lack of knowledge and ability to execute scientifically informed
interventions that would reliably yield a net positive outcome. In certain
extreme cases, such as gene editing for predator control or genetic
alteration of reproductive strategies, caution is particularly warranted.
While these approaches hold potential, our understanding of the complex
ecological interactions and long-term consequences is still limited.
Therefore, it is crucial to exercise prudence and refrain implementation
until we have a more comprehensive understanding of the potential risks and
benefits associated with such interventions.
However, rather than viewing this as a justification for inaction, it should
instead motivate us to actively position ourselves, such as through research
endeavors, to discover the most effective and safe approaches for
alleviating wild animal suffering. This calls for a proactive pursuit of
knowledge, with the ultimate aim of developing optimal strategies to address
the challenges faced by wild animals. This is precisely why I strongly
advocate for an urgent moral shift, aiming to transform the value
orientation of relevant research. By doing so, we can progressively create
the conditions necessary to ensure that wild animals have the best possible
lives.
______
Catia Faria is an assistant professor in Moral Philosophy at the Department
of Philosophy and Society at Complutense University of Madrid. She is a
founding member and currently serves on the board of the Centre for Animal
Ethics at Pompeu Fabra University in Barcelona. Her research primarily
focuses on normative and applied ethics, specifically exploring the
intersection of animal ethics, feminist ethics, and AI ethics. She has a
particular interest in understanding the impact of our present decisions on
the lives of future sentient individuals and how to decrease the risk of
generating astronomic suffering. She has published extensively on topics
such as wild animal suffering, speciesism, and the ethical tensions that
arise between animal ethics and environmental ethics. Her most recent book,
titled Animal Ethics in the Wild was published by Cambridge University
Press. Alongside her academic pursuits, she is an animal and feminist
activist.
Centre for Animal Ethics
Last paper:
Vulnerability and the Ethics of Environmental Enhancement
Bad Science Adversely Affects Animals' Emotions and Reality.
Catia Faria is a PhD in Moral Philosophy from Pompeu Fabra University and a founding member of the Center for Animal Ethics at the same university. She is a professor of moral philosophy in the Department of Philosophy and Society at the Complutense University of Madrid. She has been a postdoctoral researcher at the Portuguese Foundation for Science and Technology. She works in normative and applied ethics, in particular, on issues of animal ethics, feminist ethics, and the ethics of artificial intelligence.
Return to Book Recommendations
Read more at Book Directory